Criticisms of Mill rebutted
According to
Diana Coole (1988), Mill failed to consider that:
"... husbands would lack power and incentive to exploit genuinely
equal women, or that women's economic contribution to the household
might engender an equivalent obligation on men to share the
housework."
[Coole, D, 1988 p.145]
Yet what Mill actually wrote regarding women's participation in the
workforce was:
"If she undertakes any additional portion, it seldom relieves her
from this, but only prevents her from performing it properly."
(Mill, J S, 1869
par. 2.16)
and despite the judgemental nature of the remark in his use of the word
"properly" (and indeed possibly because of - insofar as it may be in the
woman's own judgement as to whether either of her
roles is carried out
"properly" to her own satisfaction), Mill here acknowledged what for many
women, one hundred years later, had become a juggling act between career
and their
role in the home, when every discussion about the liberation of women was
ultimately reduced to who was responsible for the washing up!
This is more
an indication of Mill's understanding of human nature than any
shortsightedness on his part. He perceived, at the time of writing, that
one of the immediate effects of women entering the public sphere,
conditions at the time being that men had no experience of or disposition
towards mundane domestic responsibilities, would result in women continuing
to be responsible for more than their fair share of domestic tasks, whilst
bearing the additional burden of earning a wage and maintaining the
subsequent lifestyle changes that this might entail - such as having a
larger house to maintain, a more lavish lifestyle in terms of entertaining
etc.
Mill may not have perceived that the same conditions would apply over
hundred years later, but Coole must surely have been aware that, despite
"engendering an equivalent obligation", in practice married women, whether
contributing financially or not, continue to retain the lion's share of
domestic responsibility to this day.
Furthermore, in criticism of Mill, Coole employs Harriet Taylor's argument
that:
"A woman who contributes materially to the support of the family
cannot be treated in the same contemptuously tyrannical manner as one
who, however she may toil as a domestic drudge, is dependant on the
man for subsistence."
[Taylor, H, 1851, quoted
Coole, D, 1988, p.145]
in order to show that Taylor was more radical than Mill, and he less of a
feminist. Yet experience in modern times has shown that many men continue
to tyrannise their wives, whether contributing financially or not,
experience of which Taylor would have been unaware, but of which Coole,
unless totally sheltered from reality, must surely be aware.
Whilst Taylor's ideas may well be described as more radical than those of
Mill, they may also be described as naive in that, twenty years after
The
Enfranchisement of Women
(1851) was published, no appreciable change had taken
place in women's position vis-a-vis their male partners or their legal
status. Mill, on the other hand, understood politics and understood that
it was necessary to appeal to men, who after all held the power to effect
change, in a rational and non-threatening way. Major change in the
traditional order takes time to achieve, as witnessed by the fact that it
was not until one hundred years after The Subjection of Women was
published that the
1969 Matrimonial Property Act ensured an equal distribution of
assets on divorce by stating that the woman's work as housewife or wage
earner should be counted an equal contribution to creating the family home.
It is necessary to separate out the feasible from the radical and
move forward at a pace that is acceptable to those who wield the power, and
particularly so, as argued by Mill, in the case where those who wield the
power are also those who benefit most from their current position. In
comparing the position of women in marriage to that of slaves, Mill argued
that the task of achieving full equality would be arduous since the
subjection was enshrined in custom and tradition and men were naturally
indisposed towards change from a pattern of life that suited their
purposes. Slavery at that time had been abolished throughout Europe, yet
the slavery of women continued, albeit in a more refined, institutionalised
form. As it had taken so long to abolish slavery, when only the few stood
to benefit from it, Mill argued that it was no surprise that, with every
man in the world standing to benefit, it would take much longer to abolish
the subjection of women.
"Instead of being, to most of its supporters, a thing desirable
chiefly in the abstract, or, like the political ends usually
contended for by factions, of little private importance to any but
the leaders; it comes home to the person and hearth of every male
head of a family, and of everyone who looks forward to being so."
(Mill, J S, 1869
par. 1.8)
Conclusion
This essay asserts that the family is indeed a good model for
political
society, that it was so in 1869 and, despite the many changes that have
taken place since (and obviously taking account of the current diversity
that exists whereby it may be more appropriate to refer to households than
families) it remains so in 1997. We are all born into families, or
households, and into an existing form of political society. The one should
reflect the other insofar as each individual's early experiences of life
occur with in the society of the family and their preparation for life
thereafter is established therein. In addition, the morality of a society
is reflected by those chosen to represent it in a national and global
sense, those most visible to the world outside are seen as representative
of the people that they purport to represent. A society that subjects
women to a form of slavery cannot criticise one which enslaves other human
beings, a society which holds people prisoners because of their political
beliefs cannot criticise another for doing likewise, a society which
pollutes the atmosphere via its manufacturing methods cannot criticise one
which destroys forests to provide homes and livelihoods for its people.
What is good for the goose must also be good for the gander.
Bibliography
Coole, D. 1988 Women in Political Society
Hemel Hempstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf
Mill, J.S. 1848
Principles of Political Economy , section "On the Probable
Futurity of the Labouring Classes"
Mill, J.S. 1869 The
Subjection
of Women
Rossi, A. 1970 "Sentiment and Intellect: The Story of John
Stuart Mill
and Harriet Taylor" in A Rossi (Editor)
Essays on Sex and Equality Chicago: Chicago University Press
Taylor, Harriet 1851
"Enfranchisement of Women" The
Westminster Review 1851
Warnock, M. 1985 Introduction to the Everyman edition of A
Vindication
of the Rights of Woman (Wollstonecraft, M, 1792) and The Subjection
of Women
(Mill, J S, 1869)
Everyman's Library
Mill's personal declaration written two months prior to his marriage to
Harriet Taylor
Being about, if I am so happy as to obtain her consent, to enter into the
marriage relation with the only woman I have ever known, with whom I would
have entered into that state; and the whole character of the marriage
relation as constituted by law being such as both she and I entirely and
conscientiously disapprove, for this among other reasons, that it confers
upon one of the parties to the contract, legal power and control over the
person, property and freedom of action of the other party, independent of
her own wishes and will; I, having no means of legally divesting myself of
these odious powers (as I most assuredly would do if an engagement to that
effect could be made legally binding on me) feel it my duty to put on
record a formal protest against the existing law of marriage, in so far as
conferring such powers; and a solemn promise never in any case or under
any circumstances to use them. And in the event of marriage between Mrs
Taylor and me I declare it to be my will and intention, and the condition
of the engagement between us, that she retains in all respects whatever the
same absolute freedom of action and freedom of disposal of herself and of
all that does or may at any time belong to her, as if no such marriage had
taken place; and I absolutely disclaim and repudiate all pretension to
have acquired any rights whatever by virtue of such marriage.
6 March 1851
J S Mill
[Rossi, A, 1970, p.45-46]
Essay copyright Catriona Woolner 1997
Suggested
bibliography entry:
Woolner, Catriona 1997 Essay on John Stuart Mill, available on the
Middlesex University Web at http://studymore.org.uk/xwoolner.htm
with
in-text references to (Woolner, C. 1997).
ABC Referencing
includes general advice on
referencing internet sources as well as
printed
sources.
Study
links outside this site
Picture introduction to this site
Andrew Roberts' web Study Guide
Top
of
Page
Take a Break - Read a Poem
Click coloured words to go where you
want
Andrew Roberts likes to hear from users:
To contact him, please
use the Communication
Form